BAILII is celebrating 24 years of free online access to the law! Would you
consider making a contribution?
No donation is too small. If every visitor before 31 December gives just £1, it
will have a significant impact on BAILII's ability to continue providing free
access to the law.
Thank you very much for your support!
[New search]
[Help]
‘Designer
donors’?: Tissue-typing and the regulation of pre-implantation genetic
diagnosis
Colin Gavaghan,
Lecturer in Medical Law, University of
Glasgow
[email protected]Copyright
© Colin Gavaghan 2004
First published in Web Journal of Current
Legal Issues
Summary
The attempts by Shahana and Raj Hashmi to produce a child that would serve
as a life-saving tissue donor for their existing child was almost guaranteed
to provoke reference to ‘designer’ and ‘spare parts’
babies. The decision by the Court of Appeal to allow the Human Fertilisation
& Embryology Authority to license this practice, and the conditions the
Authority put in place, reassured some commentators that a sensible compromise
had been found. This article argues, however, that the court’s decision
was legally questionable, that the HFEA’s conditions were arbitrary
and ethically muddled, and that overall, the regulation of tissue typing in
the UK lacks coherence and consistency.
Contents
1. Introduction
When Robert Nozick coined the term ‘Genetic Supermarket’ in
1974, he was writing in an era when even in vitro fertilisation (IVF) was
undreamt of by most lay persons. (Nozick, 1986, 315n.) The question of parents
actually being able to make choices about the genetic composition of their
offspring was no more than an admittedly fascinating thought experiment, firmly
rooted in the realm of the hypothetical. Indeed, for the next quarter of a
century, the debate remained a largely theoretical one; although the
increasingly widespread availability of IVF rendered the possibility more
plausible, the actual ‘hard cases’ that so engaged ethicists
intrigued by the notion of the Genetic Supermarket did not
materialise.
In the first few years of the Twenty-first Century, however,
several instances have arisen in the UK where couples have sought to use
pre-implantation genetic diagnosis (PGD) technology to make precisely these
kinds of choices. Inevitably, these attempts have proved controversial. Two
areas in particular have provided intriguing insights into the manner in which
the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority (HFEA) - the body entrusted
with regulating such technology - will discharge that obligation. The first,
sex pre-selection, has recently been the subject of a lengthy consultation
process, the result of which seems to have confirmed public support for the
HFEA’s earlier decision to prohibit such choices.
The second area of interest, the selection of tissue-compatible embryos to act
as donors, has produced a considerably more equivocal response from the HFEA.
It has also, as explained below, given rise to a confrontation between Parliament
and the body it created, and, ultimately, to a challenge in the courts to the
Authority’s position (
R (on the application of Quintavalle) v Human
Fertilisation and Embryology Authority [2003] EWCA Civ 667;
[2003] 3 All ER 257). Unlike sex selection, then, tissue typing
remains very much a subject of legal and ethical uncertainty.
In this article, I will outline the approach both the courts
and the HFEA have adopted to tissue typing. I will argue that while the
position adopted by the Court of Appeal is somewhat questionable, that adopted
towards this technology by the HFEA is simply untenable, relying on an eclectic
hotchpotch of ethical principles none of which is applied consistently, and
resulting ultimately in an exercise in line-drawing that seems largely arbitrary
and unfair.
2. Background to the
Hashmi
application
Zain Hashmi suffers from beta thalassaemia major, an autosomal recessive
genetic disorder which causes an abnormally high rate of breakdown of red blood
cells, leading in turn to severe anaemia. Sufferers require frequent blood
transfusions, but such a regimen can cause iron overload and consequent organ
deterioration. It is therefore considered that the only long-term solution, and
certainly the only
cure for the condition, lies in correcting the genetic
defect by bone marrow transplantation. (Lucarelli, et
al, 2001)
Without such treatment, the sufferer’s life
expectancy may well be reduced to as little as twenty-five
years.
Developments in the field of stem cell technology, however, have
obviated the need for actual bone marrow. It has been discovered that
‘[c]ord blood from neonates contains substantial
numbers of
haemopoietic stem cells, which can be harvested at
delivery, frozen,
and then transplanted to patients who would
not otherwise have a
donor’. (Lennard and Jackson, 2000) Rather than subjecting the donor to
the painful process of bone marrow retrieval in the future, then, all that would
be required would be a quantity of blood from his or her umbilical
cord.
Those wishing to utilise this technology are still faced with the
problem of finding a suitable donor, one who is Human Leukocyte Antigen (HLA)
compatible. As with all transplant situations, the likelihood of finding a
match among genetic relatives is higher than among the population at large, but
since neither Zain’s parents, nor any of his three elder siblings, were
compatible, the Hashmis undertook to have another child that could act as a
donor for Zain.
Their first attempt ended in unfortunate circumstances;
prenatal testing revealed that the child Shahana Hashmi was carrying would be
afflicted with the same condition as Zain, and she elected to have an abortion.
A second pregnancy was more successful, in that the child was unaffected, but it
quickly became apparent that this child was not a suitable tissue match and
could therefore not provide the required transplant. This outcome was not
entirely surprising; even among siblings, the chances of a child being both HLA
compatible and free from the disease were not especially favourable. Around
this time, Mrs Hashmi discussed her problem with Dr Simon Fishel, the Director
of CARE (Centres for Assisted Reproduction Limited), the ‘largest single
provider of in vitro fertilisation ... services in the United Kingdom’
(
R (on the application of Quintavalle) v Human Fertilisation and Embryology
Authority [2003] 3 All ER 257, per Lord Phillips of Worth Matravers MR, at
p259). Dr Fishel was aware of a groundbreaking procedure being piloted at the
Reproductive Genetics Institute in Chicago, and he brought this to Mrs
Hashmi’s attention. The procedure Dr Fishel described comprised five
steps:
1. the creation by in vitro fertilisation of several embryos, using gametes from
Mr and Mrs Hashmi;
2. the biopsy of a single cell from the embryos thus created;
3. the use of PGD to screen those embryos for the presence of beta thalassaemia
(henceforth referred to as Phase 1 screening);
4. simultaneous screening of the embryos to ensure HLA compatibility with Zain
(referred to by the court as ‘tissue typing’, but henceforth
referred to as Phase 2 screening);
5. jettisoning of those embryos found either to be affected by the disease, or
to be HLA-incompatible with Zain.
Although PGD had already been used for the screening out of embryos that carried
genetic diseases, Phase 2 screening had not been carried out in the UK before.
Fishel therefore enquired of the HFEA whether a licence would be granted for
such a procedure.
Top | Contents | Bibliography
3. The HFEA’s approach
to tissue typing
The HFEA appears to have found this question somewhat troubling. In 1999,
a Joint Working Party (JWP) of the HFEA and the Human Genetics Commission had
been established to consider the extent to which, and circumstances in which,
PGD should be available. When it reported in 2001, the Working Party
recommended that PGD ‘should only be available where there is a
significant risk of a serious genetic condition being present in the
embryo’. (Joint Working Group, 2001, Recommendation 11.)
The use of
PGD to ensure the birth of a suitable tissue donor had not been specifically
considered in the consultation process preceding the Report, but it is clear
that it was tacitly precluded by the terms of this Recommendation. While the
first phase of screening, to ensure the new child would itself be free from
genetic illness, would appear to fall within the terms of Recommendation 11, the
second phase, to ensure compatibility with the existing child, clearly would
not. Indeed, the Report went on (at Paragraph 29) to make this rejection of HLA
typing explicit, at least until further discussion of the perceived ethical
difficulties took place.
This further discussion was carried out by the
HFEA’s Ethics Committee, which in December 2001 published a document
entitled ‘Ethical Issues in the Creation and Selection of Preimplantation
Embryos to Produce Tissue Donors’. These new guidelines allowed for the
possibility of the use of PGD for this purpose, but such use was tightly
restricted by the conditions attached thereto. The precise nature of these
conditions will be discussed in more detail later.
The Ethics
Committee’s recommendation seems to have satisfied the HFEA that Dr
Fishel’s clinic should be granted the licence, and that the Hashmis should
therefore be permitted to make use of the two-phase screening technique (HFEA
Press Release, 13 December 2001). As will be discussed in due course, however,
not all of the Ethics Committee’s recommendations were taken on board by
the Authority.
In contrast to many accounts of developments at the
‘cutting edge’ of reproductive and genetic technology, the decision
in the case of Raj and Shahana Hashmi was widely welcomed, by the popular press
as well as the medical profession.
(1)
The HFEA, it was thought, had adroitly picked a path through an ethical
minefield, balancing the life of Zain Hashmi, and the reproductive freedom of
his parents, against the possible ethical perils of ‘designer’ and
‘spare-part babies’. The latter concerns were, it is widely
considered, reflected in the strict guidelines on tissue typing which the
Authority had published a few months prior to the decision. (‘A Summary of
the One Hundred and Thirteenth Meeting of the Human Fertilisation and Embryology
Authority’ on 29th November 2001) As then-chairwoman Ruth Deech reassured
the press, ‘[t]he authority will only approve
the treatment in
very rare circumstances and under strict
controls’. (Dyer,
2002)
4. The Select Committee on
Science and Technology
In July 2002, the HFEA’s decision in relation to tissue typing in
circumstances like those of the Hashmis, together with Chairwoman Ruth
Deech’s defence of that decision, were the subjects of criticism from the
House of Commons Select Committee on Science and Technology. (Select Committee,
2002) Noting that the public consultation process had not addressed the scenario
that arose in the Hashmi application, and that the only consideration of this
particular practice had been before the HFEA’s Ethics Committee, the
Select Committee took the view that
The HFEA’s decision to allow tissue typing in conjunction with
preimplantation genetic diagnosis went beyond the scope of its own public
consultation. It is vital that the public are taken along with decisions of such
ethical importance. (Paragraph 17)
In response to Ruth Deech’s submission that the fact that the HFEA took
the decision on PGD ‘protects Members of Parliament from direct involvement
in that sort of thing’ (Paragraph 18), the Select Committee retorted that
‘Parliament does not need protecting and democracy is not served by unelected
quangos taking decisions on behalf of Parliament.’ The Select Committee
concluded on this issue by drawing attention to the fact that ‘[a] pressure
group, Comment on Reproductive Ethics, is seeking judicial review in the High
Court on PGD on the grounds that the 1990 Act only permits distinguishing between
embryos on the basis of whether they are healthy or not or for providing treatment
services to the mother’, warning that ‘[s]hould this ultimately
be successful, Parliament's intervention may be inevitable.’
Top | Contents | Bibliography
5. The legal
challenge
The licence in question was granted on 22 February 2002, but the
HFEA’s policy decision to permit HLA tissue typing was by this time
already the subject of a legal challenge. Josephine Quintavalle, backed by the
pressure group Comment on Reproductive Ethics (CORE), sought judicial review of
the HFEA’s decision, on the grounds that it had acted
ultra vires
of the powers vested in it by the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Act
1990.
(2) The basis of Mrs
Quintavalle’s challenge lay in the wording of the 1990 Act, and comprised
four elements.
1. Section 3 of the Act prohibits the creation or use of any embryo
‘except in pursuance of a licence’.
2. Section 11 of the Act limits the circumstances within which the Authority may
issue a licence to those set out in Schedule 2.
3. Schedule 2 provides, inter alia, that a licence may only be issued if
‘it appears to the Authority to be necessary or desirable for the purpose
of providing treatment services’.
4. The definition of ‘treatment services’ is in turn spelt out in
Section 2(1), which provides the following definition: ‘“treatment
services” means medical, surgical or obstetric services provided to the
public or a section of the public for the purposes of assisting women to carry
children.’
Quintavalle’s contention was that the Hashmis’ intention to use
IVF/PGD for tissue typing did not fall within the definition of ‘providing
treatment services’, and therefore fell outwith that range of purposes for
which the Authority could legitimately issue a licence.
The
Authority responded to this challenge with two contentions of its own. Firstly,
it submitted that the testing for HLA compatibility of a cell biopsed from an
embryo did not constitute ‘use’ or ‘creation’ of an
embryo, and therefore did not require a licence within Section 3 of the Act.
While it accepted that the removal of a cell from the embryo constituted
‘use of an embryo’, whatever was done to that cell once removed, it
averred, could not be so defined.
In the event that this first submission
was rejected, the Authority submitted that it was in any event within its power
to grant a licence for this purpose, since tissue typing was ‘at least
desirable for the overall purpose of providing fertility treatment’.
Again, Quintavalle disputed this, maintaining that the purpose of tissue typing
was not to ‘assist women to carry children’, but rather, ‘to
ensure that a child born to a particular woman would have tissue that was
compatible with the tissue of a sibling.’
On 20 December 2002, at
the High Court, Maurice Kay J decided in favour of Mrs Quintavalle (
[2003] 2 All ER 105). He rejected the Authority’s contention that tissue typing did
not constitute ‘use of an embryo’, deeming it
‘inconceivable’ that Parliament could have intended to exclude such
a practice from regulation by the Authority. (pp.263-264) Having stated that the
procedure
required a licence, he then went on hold that, contrary to the
second of the Authority’s submissions, the procedure
could not be
licensed, since – as Mrs Quintavalle had contended – tissue typing
could not be said to be ‘necessary or desirable for the purpose of
assisting a woman to carry a child’.
The Authority appealed against
this decision, and was supported in that appeal by the Secretary of State for
Health, who was concerned that the decision, were it to stand, could impede the
use of PGD more generally, and specifically for the purpose of eliminating
genetic disease. The trial judge’s interpretation of the relevant section
as being restricted to allowing a woman to become pregnant and carry a child to
term was arguably not wide enough to permit screening for genetic disorders that
would not manifest themselves phenotypically until after birth. Certainly, it is
clear from CORE’s website that their objection was not solely to tissue
typing, but to PGD more
generally.
(3)On appeal,
counsel for the Authority dropped the first strand of its original case.
Carrying out the biopsy, it was conceded, clearly involved ‘using’
the embryo, and therefore must itself be ‘for the purpose of assisting a
woman to carry a child’. Since the purpose of the biopsy was to allow
tissue typing, then in order for the biopsy to fall within the terms of the Act,
so too must the tissue typing. (p264) Both parties, therefore, now agreed that,
if tissue typing were to be permitted, a licence from the Authority would
required.
The Authority’s case, rather, relied on a contention more
central to the matter, namely, that
the entire treatment, comprehending creation of the embryo, biopsy for PGD and
tissue typing, the analysis of the cell removed by the biopsy and the
implantation of the embryo, if it proved to be free of disease and a tissue
match for Zain (p264)
amounted to treatment ‘for the
purpose of assisting a woman to carry a child’. Counsel for the Authority
disputed the trial judge’s narrow interpretation of that phrase, which
seemed to see ‘treatment services’ as ‘hav[ing] as their sole
object the assistance of the physical process of producing a child.’
Rather, a broader reading of the phrase – one which, it was contended, was
closer to legislative intention – took account of the fact that, in some
circumstances, allowing a woman to eliminate the possibility of genetic disease
could be regarded as assisting her to carry a child, since ‘[w]ithout such
knowledge some women who carried genetic diseases would not be prepared to have
children.’
Were it to be accepted that PGD for the ‘screening
out’ of genetic disease fell within the definition, counsel for the
Authority went on, it followed that the purpose for which Mrs Hashmi wished to
use PGD should also be so regarded, since
In the same way tissue typing would assist Mrs Hashmi to carry a child, for her
wish to do so was conditional upon knowing that the birth of that child would be
capable of saving the life and health of Zain.
When
challenged as to whether such a wide reading of the Act could allow PGD for the
selection of
any traits to be regarded as ‘assisting’, and
thence the subject of a possible licence, counsel for the Authority conceded
this possibility, but regarded the policing of the use of this technology to be
the proper responsibility of the Authority, and not a reason to read the
governing legislation restrictively.
Counsel for Mrs Quintavalle
responded by reiterating his insistence that ‘treatment services’
should be interpreted narrowly, as referring only to measures required to
overcome problems in conceiving and maintaining a pregnancy. To this, however,
he added the second claim that, even if the term could be extended to include
measures to screen out genetic defects, what the Hashmis sought was a step
further even than this, being designed ‘to reject healthy and viable
embryos because they lacked some desired characteristic.’
In
considering the respective merits of these submissions, the Court of Appeal
placed considerable importance on the intent of the framers of the 1990 Act.
The Master of the Rolls, Lord Phillips of Worth Matravers, was impressed by the
argument from counsel for the Authority to the effect that Parliament tacitly
permitted screening of embryos for genetic abnormalities. Counsel had pointed
to Paragraph 3(2)(b) of Schedule 2, which permits the licensing of embryo
research activities for the purpose of ‘developing methods for detecting
the presence of gene or chromosome abnormalities in embryos before
implantation’. If, he argued, Parliament specifically made allowance for
research into such screening, it would be strange indeed if it intended
to prohibit the screening itself. Lord Phillips found this argument
persuasive.
(4)Parliamentary
intent, then, had not been specifically to prohibit embryo screening; but did it
follow that it had been specifically
permitted? Did screening fall
within the definition of ‘assisting women to carry children’?
Though admitting that his initial reaction was to agree with the trial judge,
i.e. that the phrase should be interpreted narrowly as applying only to
‘treatment designed to assist the physical processes from fertilisation to
the birth of a child’ (p270), Lord Phillips eventually came to the view
that screening could fall within this definition. An unwillingness to risk the
birth of a child affected by a hereditary defect could, he reasoned, constitute
an impediment just as surely as a physical obstacle, and treatment which
circumvented that impediment could be regarded as ‘for the purpose of
assisting women to carry children’.
Having accepted that screening
for genetic disorder could fall within the terms of the Act, the next question
for Lord Phillips was whether this could be extended to tissue typing. While
conceding that this might be thought to amount to a step too far for the
Authority, Lord Phillips was not prepared to draw a distinction between those
cases of PGD that are intended to screen out genetic disease, and those designed
to select other traits, such as HLA compatibility:
My conclusion is that whether the PGD has the purpose of producing a child free
from genetic defects, or of producing a child with stem cells matching a sick or
dying sibling, the IVF treatment that includes the PGD constitutes
‘treatment for the purpose of assisting women to bear children’.
(p271)
In short, these were matters which Parliament had
intended for the Authority to decide, and the Authority had acted perfectly
properly in exercising this discretion in the case of the Hashmis.
Lord
Justice Schiemann adopted a similar approach, drawing attention to the
distinction in the Act between those activities that were prohibited
altogether,
(5) and those which may
only be done in pursuit of a licence issued by the Authority. He further
concurred with Lord Phillips that ‘it was lawfully open to the Authority
to come to the conclusion that [PGD] would assist some women, who would
otherwise refrain from conception or abort either spontaneously or deliberately,
to carry a child.’ (pp.275-276) In a somewhat curious phrase, he stated
his view that ‘paragraph 1(1)(d) is wide enough to embrace ensuring that
the embryo does not suffer from a genetic defect and tissue
incompatibility.’
Whether an embryo may meaningfully be said to
‘suffer’ from tissue incompatibility is a moot point – any
suffering, it might be assumed, will be on the part of the sibling that will be
denied a transplant – but again, the reasoning seems to be that, since the
principal reason for the pregnancy is the creation of a donor, then the
inability to ensure that the next child will be a tissue match will constitute
an obstacle to the pregnancy. As such, providing such a guarantee may be
regarded as ‘assisting women to carry children’.
To the
concern that such a ruling could open the proverbial floodgates to any choices
prospective parents might want to make about their children’s genetic
constitution, provided such choices were stated as preconditions of their birth,
Lord Schiemann was, like Lord Phillips, prepared to entrust the policing of this
to the Authority:
I point out in conclusion that Parliament did not
impose upon the Authority any express obligation to sanction the grant of
licences even if what was proposed was indubitably necessary for the purpose of
assisting a woman to carry a child. ... If the decision of the Authority is
upheld in the present case it does not mean that parents have a right to in
vitro fertilisation for social selection purposes. (p.276)
Finally, Lord
Justice Mance also favoured an interpretation that took account of more than
allowing a woman to overcome physical obstacles to initiating and maintaining a
pregnancy. As well as considering the same background sources as his fellow
judges – the Warnock Report, the White Paper that preceded the 1990 Act
– he sought support for his position within the terms of the Act itself.
Section 13(5) of the Act, he pointed out, specifically enjoined the Authority to
have regard for the welfare of the child created thereby. That being so, he
found himself
in these circumstances left in no real doubt that the concept of “medical,
surgical or obstetric services .... for the purpose of assisting women to carry
children” was intended to embrace not merely services to assist women
physically to carry to term and give birth, but also services to assist them to
give birth to children who would be normal and healthy during their lives and
would in turn be able to have normal and healthy children.
(p.284)
The requirement, then, ‘is better served if the legislation is read
as permitting such screening.’
Top | Contents | Bibliography
6. Was the Court of Appeal
correct?
The Court of Appeal’s decision to overturn the first instance ruling
was predicated on two assumptions: firstly, that the definition of
‘treatment services’ was wide enough to encompass PGD aimed at
eliminating the possibility of a child being born with a hereditary defect; and
secondly, that this in turn could be extended to apply to screening for HLA
compatibility. I would suggest, however, that the former assumption is built
upon considerably firmer foundations than the latter.
Firstly, the
recognition by Lord Phillips MR and Mance LJ that Paragraph 3(2)(b) of Schedule
2 clearly permitted the use of embryos for research into ‘developing
methods for detecting the presence of gene or chromosome abnormalities in
embryos before implantation’ lends some credence to the claim that
Parliament envisaged screening for such abnormalities. It is, indeed, unlikely
that the framers of the Act would allow research into a procedure, but outlaw
the procedure itself.
Secondly, Mance LJ was surely correct to point
out that the requirement in Section 13(5) that consideration be paid to the
welfare of any child born as a result of treatment seems to sit uneasily with a
prohibition on screening pre-implantation embryos for even serious
disorders.
Thirdly, much of the background material referred to by the
Court – in particular, from the Warnock Report, the White Paper that
preceded the 1990 Act, and the then Secretary of State Kenneth Clarke’s
contributions to the debate as the Bill made its way through Parliament - adds
weight to the contention that the intention of the Act’s framers was to
allow screening for hereditary abnormalities.
As Lord Phillips
recognised, however, accepting that PGD for hereditary defects was permitted
within the Act was only a ‘stepping stone’ to the destination the
appellants wished to arrive at, i.e., judicial recognition that the Authority
was empowered to issue a licence for tissue typing. And that second step is one
that is taken on a decidedly slippier surface. Nothing in the background
materials to which the Court looked, nor in the other provisions of the Act,
make explicit or implicit reference to tissue typing.
An argument could
perhaps be fashioned around the Section 13(5) requirement that concern be paid
to the welfare of the child born or any other children affected by the
treatment. Juliet Tizzard, of the Progress Educational Trust, has suggested
that this might be used to draw attention to the extent to which allowing the
Hashmis to use tissue typing might further the interests of Zain in being
provided with a HLA compatible sibling. (Tizzard, 2002) This clause has caused a
degree of confusion among academic commentators perplexed as to what sort of
situation was being envisaged when it was inserted. However, it may be thought
likely that this provision was intended as a further check on the provision of
treatment – treatment providers should exercise caution if other children
are likely to be harmed as a result – rather than a justification for
treatment that would not otherwise fall within the terms of the
Act.
Equally questionable was the Court’s decision that tissue
typing could fall within the definition of ‘treatment for the purpose of
assisting women to bear children’, on the basis that, were it not
permitted, Mrs Hashmi may well not have had a further child.
‘Treatment’, it might be thought, carries some connotation of
restoring normal functioning after, or ameliorating the effects of, some
disability or disease. Walter Glannon, for example, speaks of
‘treatment’ as being aimed at ‘avoiding harm to people and
benefiting them by allowing them to realize their interest in having healthy
lives.’ (Glannon, 2001, 79) We may well speak of ‘assisting’
people to overcome other obstacles to achieving what they want, but we would on
the whole speak of ‘treating’ them only if their health was
impaired.
It could, of course, be argued that Mrs Hashmi’s status
as a carrier of the thalassaemia with which Zain was afflicted compromised her
interest in a healthy life, in that she was disabled from being able to bear a
child with an average chance of being free from serious disability. If this
view were taken, then PGD to screen out affected embryos could perhaps be seen
as ‘treatment’ for that disorder. However, her inability to
guarantee that any child she bore would be a suitable tissue match for Zain was
not the result of any pathology or deficiency, but simply the nature of normal
genetic inheritance. To categorise Phase 2 screening as ‘treatment’
seems to stretch the definition beyond reasonable usage.
7. The role of the
HFEA
Whatever the legal merits of its decision, the Court of Appeal seems to
have been considerably less troubled than the Select Committee by the prospect
of entrusting policy decisions about PGD and tissue typing to the HFEA. How,
then, has the HFEA discharged that obligation? Although, as we have seen, the
Authority was prepared to permit tissue-typing in circumstances like those of
the Hashmis, it appeared to be greatly concerned to demonstrate that they had in
no way thrown open the floodgates to ‘designer babies’, attaching a
series of strict conditions to that decision.
a. Condition 1: Last
resorts and necessary evils
The first two of the conditions which the Ethics Committee recommended, and
the HFEA subsequently accepted, require that ‘all other possibilities of
treatment and sources of tissue for the affected child should have been
explored’ and that the use of HLA typing should be limited to
‘severe or life-threatening’ cases. In short, the HFEA requires
that this technology be utilised only in cases of direst need, and even then,
only as a last resort. In so doing, it might be thought that the HFEA is making
a statement about the pro tanto wrongness of the technology. If, after all,
there were nothing inherently wrong in the practice, there would be no need to
find such compelling justification for its use.
What, then, might the
Ethics Committee – and ultimately the Authority, which accepted its
recommendations on these points – regard as being ethically problematic
about using PGD for tissue-typing? And is it reasonable to conclude that these
concerns were more adequately addressed when the conditions listed are met? At
the outset of its consideration, the Committee identified three questions which
it hoped would guide it in framing its recommendations:
- Is PGD with HLA typing compatible with the ‘welfare of the
unborn child’?
- Is licensing PGD with HLA typing compatible with the public good?
- Can morally significant criteria be found to demarcate ‘acceptable’
and ‘unacceptable’ reasons for the conception and selection of
embryos?
The last of these three questions might be thought to presuppose the answers
to the first two, in that no such demarcation would be necessary unless there
actually existed unacceptable reasons. It seems, therefore, that the question
of the pro tanto wrongness of PGD/HLA rests in the first instance on its likely
impact on this question of welfare, and in the second on the likely impact
on the public good.
Welfare of the unborn
child
In considering the welfare of the future child, the Ethics Committee
considered both a fairly traditional formulation of the ‘welfare
principle’, asking ‘whether the outcome of the technique adversely
shifts the balance of benefit and harm’, (Para. 2.14) together with a more
unusual formulation where the Committee considered the proposition that:
It could be suggested that positive consideration of the welfare of the child
requires respect for beings as ends and that the putative child be treated not
merely as a means to a further end but also as an “end in itself”.
(at para. 2.9)
The first, and more straightforward, of
these conceptions of welfare asks whether the donor child will experience a
balance of benefit over harm as a result of the technique in question. Such
concern may seem entirely valid in this context. Is it not reasonable to take
account of the possible emotional and psychological burdens that may be
experienced by a child who grows up knowing that it was created for such a
purpose? That their relationship with the parents who conceived them for that
reason, or with the sibling they saved, will be adversely affected?
Such
possible objections begin to look less compelling, however, when we consider
what the alternative was for the child in question. Because of course, for this
particular child, the alternative to being born as a tissue donor is not to be
born into a more conventional family setting, but rather, not to be born at
all. This counter-intuitive but compelling conclusion was brought to
prominence by Derek Parfit in his seminal philosophical work, Reasons and
Persons, and it has been highly influential upon many writers in the field
of bioethics (Heyd, 1994; Roberts, 1998; Gavaghan, 2000). Parfit’s
conclusion rested on the understanding that our identity is dependent upon the
precise combination of sperm and ovum from which we developed; had two different
gametes been combined, my parents would have had a different child. Though it
would have had the same parents, same environment, possibly the same name, it
would not have been me.
Once this is accepted, then it becomes
difficult to conclude that the child created as a tissue donor is harmed by
those decisions upon which its very existence is dependent. Unless we foresee
that its life is likely to be so unremittingly awful that existence itself will
be a burden, we must conclude that it is better off (or at least no worse off)
being born into these unusual circumstances than never being born at all.
Having identified a fairly traditional conception of the welfare of the
resultant child as one of its primary concerns, the Committee went on to
elaborate that ‘positive consideration of the welfare of the child
requires respect for beings as ends and that the putative child be treated not
simply as a means to a further end but also as an “end in
itself.”’ (para 2.9) The Kantian imperative that all humans should
be treated as ends in themselves is one that commands widespread adherence, and
it is perhaps understandable that the Committee would wish to conduct its
deliberations in that light.
What does it mean to treat someone as a
means and not as an end? As Beauchamp and Childress point out (2001), this
ethical rule is often misinterpreted as meaning simply that it is objectionable
to use someone as a means to furthering one's own objectives – something
we do every time we hire a plumber to unblock our sink or taxi driver to take us
home. Kant's imperative, in fact, did not prohibit such acts of
‘using’, but rather, warned against treating people merely as
a means and not also as an end in themselves. That is to say, there is
nothing objectionable per se in using someone as a means, provided I do
not lose sight of the fact that s/he is also an end in him/herself.
Alan
Donagan is a leading contemporary adherent to and interpreter of Kantian ethics.
For him
Kant’s formula of the fundamental principle may be restated in a form more
like that of the spiritual commandment that is its original: Act always so
that you respect every human being, yourself or another, as being a rational
creature. (Donagan, 1977, at p65.)
What sort of duties,
then, are owed to a being by virtue of its status as a rational creature? Much
of Donagan’s book is given over to a discussion of this question, and he
identifies various ‘precepts’ that derive from the core imperative.
He maintains, for example, that ‘it is impermissible for anybody at will
to use force upon another’, (p.82) a precept that itself gives rise to
derivative precepts prohibiting killing, inflicting bodily injury or holding
another in slavery (p.83); that ‘[i]t is impermissible not to promote the
well-being of others by actions in themselves permissible’; that it is
impermissible to lie (p.88); and that there exists a duty (subject, as are
almost all of these ‘first-order precepts’, to certain exceptions)
to obey the law (p.109).
One striking aspect of these precepts is that
they seem to give rise to a more obvious case in favour of HLA-typing in
cases like those of the Hashmis and Whitakers than they support the contrary
position. For while Donagan has nothing to say about the sort of scenario about
which the Committee were asked to deliberate, the precept that imposes a
positive duty of beneficence - ‘[i]t is impermissible not to promote the
well-being of others by actions in themselves permissible’ – gives
arise to a pro tanto obligation to rescue Zain. Of course, the caveat ‘by
actions in themselves permissible’ prevents us from leaping too readily to
this conclusion. But nonetheless, a first reading of Donagan’s precepts
seems to see the scales tilt in favour not only of allowing HLA-typing in
life-or-death cases such as those under consideration, but perhaps in cases of
less serious illness too; the precept, after all, does not stop at imposing a
duty to save life, but rather speaks of ‘promot[ing] the well-being of
others’.
The question that remains is whether the actions in
question are ‘in themselves permissible’. It is impossible to
advance a definitive answer to this without attempting a fuller study of
deontological ethics, a task beyond the remit of this article. However, on an
admittedly superficial reading, it is not obvious that HLA-typing would
contravene the duty to respect the new child as an end in itself in any of the
ways specifically identified by Donagan. The new child would certainly not be
killed, exposed to bodily harm or enslaved. The positive duty to promote its
interests is arguably meaningless in a context where the future child does not
presently possess any interests, and there is certainly no obvious sense in
which such a possibility exists but is being neglected. And duties in relation
to truthfulness, honouring contracts, and obeying the law are irrelevent in this
context.
What the Kantian imperative seems to require, then – at
least as Donagan interprets it – is that the well-being of Zain Hashmi
(and Charlie Whitaker, considered below) should be promoted unless it can be
demonstrated that some other aspect of the duty – presumably as owed to
the new child - is being violated. It is for scholars of Kant, of Donagan and
of such duty-based ethics more generally to ascertain whether any such competing
obligation exists and, if so, whether it can outweigh what Donagan clearly
recognises as a duty to the existing, suffering children. For the purposes of
this article, it is sufficient to note that it is by no means uncontroversial or
obvious that this ethical obligation to which the Ethics Committee attached such
weight, namely to respect all humans as ends in themselves and as rational
beings, weighs against HLA-typing, either in life-or-death cases or in
cases where it is only well-being rather than life itself that is at stake.
Indeed, it may even be that this obligation – contrary to the Ethics
Committee’s apparent assumption - pulls in the opposite
direction.
A similar approach to the Kantian imperative has been advanced
by Walter Glannon, this time in relation to the possibility of reproductive
human cloning. Glannon invites us to imagine a (far from implausible) scenario
wherein
the parents of a recently deceased or dying child want to clone an individual
who is genetically identical to that child and thus “replace” it to
compensate for their loss or else carry on the family line.
(Glannon, 2001, p118.)
Glannon acknowledges that, if
‘the sole intent of the parents is replacement or compensation, then the
cloned individual would be treated solely as a means,’ and that this
‘would deny the intrinsic dignity and worth one possesses in virtue of the
fact that one is a human agent for the capacity for reason.’ However, for
Glannon, the motives with which the clone was created would be less important
than the manner in which it is treated throughout its life:
if the clone were loved and treated with the dignity and respect commanded by
its intrinsic worth, then cloning might be morally justifiable on Kantian
grounds. Although the intention to clone the child suggests that he or she
would be treated instrumentally, the fact that the child is treated as a unique
individual once she exists is enough to dispel any moral qualms about the
parent’s behavior.
In short, ‘how one is
treated by others over the course of one’s life is more morally
significant than the reasons for causing one to exist.’ (at
p.120)
Yet even if this is an erroneous interpretation of the duty, and
that HLA-typing presents greater difficulties for the duty to respect the new
child as an end in itself than has been recognised here, it is by no means clear
that the recommendations at which the Committee arrived would follow from this.
For if it is felt that ‘being born to be a donor’ is incompatible
with being treated as an end in oneself, then it is difficult to see how this is
only so when the anticipated donee is a parent, rather than a sibling. In
neither case is the prospective child able to consent to the donation, nor of
course to its creation. In both cases the decision involves consideration for a
party other than the putative child itself. In both scenarios, in other words,
the donor child is being created at least partly as a means to some other end.
The next section will consider this most perplexing of conditions.
b. Condition 2: The
parental exception
The fact that the Committee had wandered into areas of ethical confusion,
and perhaps departed from its original remit, became clearest when it came to
consider the possibility of utilising this technology to provide a tissue
donation to a parent. Among its final recommendations, it proposed that
‘because it [the Committee] favours a principle of qualified parental
decision-making with respect to the use of the technique the technique should
not be available where the intended tissue recipient is a parent.’
(Para. 3.15, original emphasis) No further justification is offered for such a
condition in this paragraph, and it is necessary to search the remainder of the
document in some depth to locate some indication of the Committee’s
reasoning.
Paragraph 2.21 concluded with the claim that ‘it appears
prima facie to be morally less acceptable than selecting an embryo to
provide tissue to treat a sibling, as it seems to replace concern with another
with concern for oneself.’ There are several observations that could be
made regarding this assertion. Firstly, it may be seen to conflate that which
is morally acceptable with that which is morally commendable.
Undertaking a physically, emotionally and perhaps financially demanding process
such as IVF and pregnancy in order to save the life of another may perhaps scale
heights of altruism and selflessness greater than undertaking these burdens to
save one’s own life. But that is not to say that the latter course of
action is morally unacceptable. To make out the case for moral unacceptability,
the Committee would need to have demonstrated some aspect of the treatment that
contravened some ethical principle.
Secondly, the Committee’s
assessment perhaps overlooks the contribution and sacrifice of the other parent.
If, for example, it had been the father who suffered from a debilitating and
life-threatening condition requiring stem cell transfusion, and if the couple
had undergone the same procedure in attempt to find a suitable donor, would the
requisite element of sacrifice and altruism not have been displayed in the
mother’s willingness to go through ova retrieval, embryo implantation,
pregnancy and labour to save her husband?
Neither the 1990 Act nor
the common law require parents to have wholly or primarily non-selfish motives
when they act on behalf of their children. The parent whose selfish decision
happens to coincide with his child’s interests will not have his motives
scrutinised for any hint of self-interest. Why, we might ask, should such an
unfeasibly high standard be set for prospective parents seeking to use
PGD-HLA?
It might also be asked whether it is not invariably the case
that, by the very fact of its conception and birth, a child is serving as a
means to some other end? It is perhaps unlikely that any pregnancies are
commenced wholly or predominantly out of beneficence towards the future child.
Couples or individuals have children for a wide variety of reasons, ranging from
the fulfilment of long-harboured life plans to unwelcome accidents, via myriad
psychologically complicated motivations involving self-fulfilment, tradition,
peer expectation, strengthening ailing relationships and a – perhaps
subconscious – quest for some sort of genetic immortality. As Julian
Savulescu has said:
Parents have many desires related to their children: perhaps to have a
companion, to have a friend to the first child, or to hold a marriage together.
It is unlikely that any parent ever desires a child solely as an end in itself.
... Provided that parents love their child as an end in itself, there is no
problem with the child's life also fulfilling some of the parents’ desires
for their own lives. (Savulescu, 1999, p373.)
It is also
entirely common to hear parents citing a desire for companionship for an
existing child as a reason.
Whatever the precise reasoning, however, the
fact that a couple
want to be genetic parents is a selfish, or at best a
mixed, motive, just as surely as the fact that one of them needs a donation of
stem cells. It may be that in other times and in other societies, couples
greeted the news of pregnancy with a stoical acceptance that they were
fulfilling an unhappy duty, but it would be difficult to see this as a
preferable state of affairs to that wherein the forthcoming birth of a child is
seen as a joyous event for all concerned. For the most part, we want parents to
satisfy their own wants and ambitions when bringing a child into the world. Of
course, if these wants and ambitions were likely to harm the child once it is
existence – if the child was wanted as a slave or a sacrifice, for example
- that might be problematic. But the mere fact that the creation of a life
symbiotically benefits the parents is not only accepted, but is for the most
part expected and welcomed.
Considered through the lens of the welfare of
the future child, what the Hashmis sought to do was unproblematic, for precisely
the reasons identified by Derek Parfit and discussed earlier in this article.
But even for those concerned about such children ‘being treated as an end
in oneself and not merely a means’, it is far from clear that the putative
Hashmi child would be so treated; provided it is treated with respect, dignity
and compassion once it is born, the categorical imperative is satisfied in its
regard. Furthermore, I submit, this would be so whether the intended recipient
of the transplant is a sibling, a parent, or any other third party.
Whether the parents are motivated by altruistic concern for other children,
or selfish concern for their own health, they are nonetheless viewing the new
child as a means to some other end. But provided they do not view it, and more
importantly do not treat it,
only as a means, they have not violated
its interest in being treated with respect.
Top | Contents | Bibliography
8. The Whitaker case: an
arbitrary distinction?
The Quintavalle challenge, then, demonstrated that the Court of Appeal was
content to entrust to the HFEA the responsibility for ensuring that PGD is used
only in ‘appropriate’ circumstances. The manner in which this task
is being carried out has, I submit, been cast into doubt by the apparent ethical
confusion underlying the conditions attached to the decision about HLA tissue
typing. Even greater reason for dissatisfaction lies in the Authority’s
handling of the next application for a licence to carry out tissue typing.
Charlie Whitaker suffered from Diamond Blackfan Anaemia (DBA), a rare
blood disorder requiring day-long blood transfusions. In that the condition is
painful, debilitating and impossible to cure without transfusion, it is
analogous to Zain Hashmi’s thalassaemia. The distinction, upon which the
HFEA placed so much reliance, is that DBA is rarely a hereditary condition;
indeed, tests of Charlie’s parents, Michelle and Jayson Whitaker, revealed
that they were not carriers, and that Charlie’s condition was attributable
to a spontaneous mutation.
As already noted, the Joint Working
Party’s Recommendation 11 restricted PGD to cases where the embryo being
screened was itself at significant risk of developing a particular genetic
condition. While the future Hashmi child satisfied this criterion – both
Shahana and Raj Hashmi being asymptomatic carriers - any future child the
Whitakers may have would be at no greater than average risk of developing DBA.
The terms of the Recommendation, therefore, would not be satisfied in the latter
case.
However, the HFEA Ethics Committee, charged specifically with the
role of considering the ethics of HLA tissue-typing, reached an entirely
different conclusion. Paragraph 3.14 of the Committee’s Report addressed
precisely the scenario in which the Whitakers found themselves, and recommended
that PGD should be available in those circumstances. In announcing in August
2002 that the Whitakers would be denied access to PGD for tissue-typing only,
the HFEA acted against the recommendation of its own Ethics Committee in this
matter. While it is of course free to do so, it is difficult to discern what
ethical or legal basis the HFEA was relying on when it made this decision.
The ethical
approach
The Minutes of the first HFEA meeting after the Ethics Committee’s
Report contain only a fairly cursory discussion of the issue:
Members felt that to allow PGD for tissue typing alone would run contrary to the
requirements of the welfare of the child assessment. Therefore, it was agreed
that tissue typing using PGD should only be offered where PGD was already
necessary to avoid the passing on of a serious genetic disorder. (HFEA,
2001b)
As discussed earlier, the Ethics Committee had in
fact identified the ‘putative child’s actual moral, psychological,
social and physical welfare’ as an issue of great significance. (Ethics
Committee, 2001) Its Report considered both a fairly traditional formulation of
the ‘welfare principle’, asking ‘whether the outcome of the
technique adversely shifts the balance of benefit and harm’, (at Para.
2.14) together with a more unusual formulation where the Committee considered
the proposition that:
It could be suggested that positive consideration of the welfare of the child
requires respect for beings as ends and that the putative child be treated not
merely as a means to a further end but also as an “end in itself”.
(at Para. 2.9)
It is unclear which of these concepts of
‘welfare’ the HFEA felt to be compromised by the Whitakers’
application. The first version, concerned with the prospect of harm to the
future child, seems to be answerable in terms of Parfit’s Non-Identity
Principle in exactly the same manner as in the Hashmi scenario. Unless we can
predict with confidence that either child will suffer a net balance of harms
over benefits as a result of its existence, it is impossible to conclude that
the very fact of its creation constitutes a harm to it.
Had the HFEA
contended that the Whitakers would be likely to neglect or abuse the new child,
regarding it literally as an instrument to save Charlie’s life, to be
tossed aside when that end was attained, then there may have been a case to
answer. As far as can be ascertained from the Minutes of the November meeting,
however, the HFEA at no point seriously considered the possibility that the new
child would be treated in a manner likely to give rise to such
concerns.
The only indication of the thinking that led the HFEA to
conclude that the future child’s welfare would be compromised lies in the
Minutes’ brief reference to ‘the psychological burden that may be
placed on a child who was an “engineered” match as opposed to a
‘natural’ match.’ (HFEA, 2001b) The terminology used here
might be considered imprecise and unfortunate. The Whitakers did not seek to
alter the genetic makeup of their future child, as the term
‘engineered’ is ordinarily thought to denote. If the distinction
the HFEA sought to address was between a ‘selected’ match as opposed
to a ‘randomly occurring’ match, then it is not apparent how the
former child would be at a disadvantage. In both cases, there will be an
expectation that the child will act as a donor.
Similarly, the second of
the Ethics Committee’s conceptions of ‘welfare’ seems
ill-suited to distinguish between the Hashmis case and that of the Whitakers.
The concern that the putative child be considered ‘not merely as a means
to a further end but also as an “end in itself”’ reflects the
widely recognised Kantian principle that requires that we regard the new child
as an end in itself, taking account of its interests and rights, and not merely
as an instrument of someone else’s welfare.
As discussed earlier
in this article, such a principle may – although by no means
uncontroversially – be accommodated within a consideration of the welfare
of the future child. However, as explained above, it is by no means clear that
the creation of a child to serve as a donor violates this principle –
provided that child is treated with the dignity and respect due to an
individual, then it has not been treated solely as a means. Furthermore, it is
far from clear how it serves to distinguish the two cases. Both families sought
to have a new child, and to use PGD to select that child, at least partly for
the good of an existing child. Even if we were to accept that ‘first
phase’ PGD, for disease screening, was in the interests of that future
child (a conclusion that is difficult, if not impossible, to reconcile with the
Non-Identity Principle), it is surely the case that in both scenarios, the use
of ‘second phase’ screening, for HLA tissue-typing, was sought
exclusively for the benefit of another party. If the HFEA’s concern is
with preventing embryos being screened wholly for the benefit of someone else,
then it is difficult to see how it was any more justified for the Hashmis than
for the Whitakers.
While medico-legal academics may have hoped that the Whitakers would contest
the HFEA’s refusal through the courts, affording us the opportunity to
ascertain judicial views on the validity of the distinction upon which the Authority
relied, the Whitakers availed themselves of a different option. Instead of investing
money and time in a potentially fruitless challenge to the obstacles facing
them in the UK, they opted instead to travel to the USA, where no such regulatory
difficulties presented themselves. In June 2003, after treatment in the Chicago
Reproductive Genetics Institute, Michelle Whitaker gave birth to Jamie, a healthy
son whose stem cells could be used to treat his brother Charlie. (Dobson, 2003)
It is a somewhat ironic facet of the tale that the Hashmis, whose efforts to
conceive a donor child were supported by the HFEA and the courts, have as yet
been unable to do so.
Top | Contents | Bibliography
8. Conclusion
The Court of Appeal’s decision in the
Quintavalle case, and in
particular its recognition that non-pathological factors could be considered as
suitable matters for ‘treatment’ in terms of the 1990 Act, could be
seen to have lent a wide margin of discretion to the HFEA in terms of granting
licences for PGD. The manner in which the Authority has exercised this
discretion, however, has afforded little room for optimism in terms of ethical
coherence or consistency. While the ethical principles identified by the
Authority and its Ethics Committee – concerning the welfare of the child,
and the Kantian requirement that it be treated as an end and not merely a means
– are respectable and widely recognised, they have been applied in a
manner that suggests only a superficial understanding of their implications. In
particular, although the welfare of the child figures prominently in these
discussions, at no point is the Non-Identity Principle explicitly considered,
nor does it appear to influence the eventual decisions at which they
arrived.
The categorical imperative (or more specifically that variation
thereof that requires that all individuals be treated not merely as means but
also as ends in themselves) was applied with apparent lack of rigour, and a
marked lack of consistency can be discerned from the manner in which it was
applied to the various permutations of circumstances that might arise. It is, I
have argued, by no means certain that creating a child to serve as a tissue
donor violates that imperative; certainly, the interpretation of the principle
adopted by Alan Donagan, one of its most influential proponents, seems almost to
suggest the very opposite.
However, even if the view is taken that creating a child with the principal
motive of having it serve as a tissue donor does in fact amount to a contravention
of the Kantian imperative, and even if it is accepted that this in turn amounts
to harming the child, it is by no means obvious how this provides a valid ground
to distinguish between the (a) Hashmi scenario, (b) the Whitaker scenario, and
(c) scenario where the intended recipient is a parent. In all three cases, the
child is being created to serve as a donor, and in all three cases Phase 2 screening
is being carried out precisely for that end. Either the Kantian imperative is
violated by none of these – as I suggest – or it is violated by
all three. That being so, the decisions and rules arrived at by the HFEA certainly
seem arbitrary, and it may not even be unduly cynical to suggest that they are
motivated more by a desire to maintain an appearance of control - in the face
of Select Committee criticism and media concern about ‘designer babies’
– than about legitimate concern for the ‘welfare’ of the resulting
child. If, as the Court of Appeal’s decision in
Hashmi seems to
suggest, it is the HFEA rather than the courts that is to be entrusted with
regulating PGD, then it is incumbent upon that body to arrive at more carefully
reasoned, and consistent, rules and decisions.
Top | Contents
Bibliography
Ethics Committee of the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority,
(2001),
Ethical Issues in the Creation and Selection of Preimplantation
Embryos to Produce Tissue Donors, 22 November 2001
Joint Working
Group of the HFEA and Human Genetics Commission (2001),
Outcome of the Public
Consultation on Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis, November 2001
Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority (2001a), Press Release, 13
December 2001, ‘HFEA to allow tissue typing in conjunction with
preimplantation genetic diagnosis’ (HFEA, 2001a)
Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority,(2001b):
A Summary of the One
Hundred and Thirteenth Meeting of the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority
on 29th November 2001, at
http://www.hfea.gov.uk/AboutHFEA/AuthorityMinutes/2001/November2001
Berkowitz,
Jonathan M., Snyder, Jack W. (1998): ‘Racism and
Sexism in Medically Assisted Conception’,
Bioethics; 12(1): 25-44
Dobson, R
(2003): ‘“Saviour sibling” is born after embryo selection in
the United States’,
British Medical Journal, 326:1416
(28June).
Donagan, A (1977):
The Theory of Morality, Chicago,
University of Chicago Press
Dyer, C. (2002): ‘Watchdog approves
embryo selection to treat 3 year old child.’
British Medical
Journal; 324: 503
Glannon, W. (2001):
Genes and Future People:
Philosophical Issues in Human Genetics, Oxford, Westview Press,
2001
Lennard, A. L., Jackson, G. H. (2000) ‘Stem cell
transplantation’.
British Medical Journal; 321:
433-437
Lucarelli, G.,
Andreani, M., Angelucci, E.
(2001) ‘The cure of thalassemia with bone marrow transplantation’
Bone Marrow Transplantation; 28: S11-3.
Savulescu, Julian (1999).
‘Sex selection: the case for’,
Medical Journal of Australia;
171(7): 373-375
(1)
See, for example, ‘Why Mr and Mrs Hashmi were right to choose life’,
Independent on Sunday, 24 February 2002; ‘The virtue of IVF’,
The Observer, 24 February
2002
(2)
The Quintavalle family were by this point no strangers to the English civil
courts, Mrs Quintavalle’s son, Bruno, having already attained prominence
by challenging – initially successfully, although he ultimately lost on
appeal to the House of Lords - the efficacy of the 1990 Act in prohibiting human
cloning (
R. (on the application of Quintavalle) v Secretary of State for
Health (2002) 63 B.M.L.R. 167,
(2003) 71 BMLR 209). It is interesting to
speculate on the extent to which the courts are likely to replace the
legislature as the primary forum within which bioethical disputes will be played
out.
(3) ‘PGD is purely and simply
another example of modern eugenics, practised ever earlier on developing human
life. ... With PGD the purpose of diagnosis is simply to identify who should
be killed. Neither for the disabled baby in the womb, nor for the disabled
embryo do you offer any choice but the final solution - death. ’ From
CORE’s Response to Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority/ Advisory
Committee on Genetic Testing Consultation Document on Preimplantation Genetic
Diagnosis, available at
http://www.corethics.org/document.asp?id=fresponse.htm&se=3&st=5
(4)
See also the judgment of Lord Justice Mance at
p.283.
(5)
Including, inter alia, placing a non-human embryo in a human, or vice versa;
keeping an embryo after the appearance of the primitive streak, and cell nuclear
replacement.
BAILII:
Copyright Policy |
Disclaimers |
Privacy Policy |
Feedback |
Donate to BAILII
URL: http://www.bailii.org/uk/other/journals/WebJCLI/2004/issue3/gavaghan3.html